Facebook is Not a Factory (But Still Exploits its Users)
This piece is posted in cooperation with the Cyborgology Blog.
Facebook’s IPO announcement has stirred much debate over the question of whether Facebook is exploiting/using/taking advantage of its users. The main problem with the recent discussion of this subject is that no one really seems to have taken the time to actually define what exploitation is. Let me start by reviewing this concept before proceeding to examine its relevance to Facebook.
Defining exploitation. The concept of exploitation came to prominence about a century and a half ago through the writings of Karl Marx, and he gave it a specific, objectively calculable definition—though, I’ll spare you the mathematical expressions. Marx starts from the assumption that value is created from labor (most people today acknowledge that value is contingent on other factors as well, but we need merely to accept that labor is one source of value for Marx’s argument to work). According to Marx, humans have an important natural relationship to the fruits of our labor, and our work is a definitive part of who we are. Modern capitalist society is unique from other periods in history because workers sell their labor time in exchange for wages (as opposed to, say, creating objects and bartering them for other objects). Capitalists accumulate money by skimming off some of the value created by worker’s labor and, so that the wages a worker receives is only a fraction of the total value he or she has created. The portion of the value created by a worker that is not returned back to that worker (after operating costs are covered) is called the rate of exploitation.
So, for example, imagine that, during one day of work, a factory worker takes $10 worth of wood and assembles a chair that retails for $60; if the worker is paid $20 in wages for that day, then rate of exploitation would equal $30/day. That is to say, the capitalist is made $30 richer each day at the expense of the worker. The real degree of exploitation, however, is best represented in relative terms. If we calculate the $30 of surplus value expropriated by the capitalist as a percentage the total value created ($60 – $10 = $50), then we find that the real degree of exploitation is 60% of the value created by the worker.
The important point here is that exploitation is an objective calculation—one that is separable from the subsequent moral debates we often have about ensuring fairness versus rewarding risk/innovation. So, if we want have a debate about the (im)morality of Facebooks’ business model—as many recent commentators are, in fact, endeavoring to do—we must first establish that exploitation objectively exists on Facebook. However, this is not as easy as it might seem. The organization of Facebook hardly resembles the “cattle-like existence” in the factories that Marx originally set out to describe. While Facebook’s users flock to the site willingly, even happily, Marx summarized the factory as a place where the worker:
does not feel content but unhappy, does not develop freely his physical and mental energy but mortifies his body and ruins his mind. . . . His labor is therefore not voluntary, but coerced; it is forced labor. It is therefore not the satisfaction of a need; it is merely a means to satisfy needs external to it. Its alien character emerges clearly in the fact that as soon as no physical or other compulsion exists, labor is shunned like the plague.
Given this apparent disconnect between the experience of factory work and social media use, we should be reluctant about merely attempting to superficially shoehorn this new phenomenon into the classic conceptual frame of exploitation. Instead, we should ask ourselves if these apparent differences have any bearing on the assumptions underlying our calculation of the rate of exploitation. Indeed, a closer examination reveals significant differences between the way exploitation is carried out in the factory and on social media.
Why do people use social media voluntarily, but avoid factory-style work whenever possible? There are two important reasons: 1.) Factory work is alienating, separating workers’ from their creative faculties to shape the nature of the objects they are laboring to produce. Social media encourages a much greater degree of self-directed creativity. 2.) Social media users are not only producers of social media but also consumers. As such, there are direct and obvious benefits to social media use, unlike the discomfort of factory work which only partially and indirectly remediated by wages. These benefits of social media use are largely immaterial: e.g., making and preserving social connections, cultivating and demonstrating taste, and telegraphing that you are “with it,” part of the in-crowd. (Sociologists call these benefits cultural, social, and symbolic capital).
Though we all can recognize that these immaterial benefits have real value, it is extremely difficult to fix a price to them. How many dollars is a friendship worth? How much culturally literacy can you purchase for $100? Moreover, because usage patterns vary so widely, different social media users are bound to derive different sorts of value from their use. That is to say, the value of these immaterial benefits is relative to the unique circumstances of each user. Because users are “compensated” through these immaterial benefits (rather than receiving conventional wages), it is extremely difficult to come up with a concrete figure for the real degree of exploitation (note: this is not really “compensation” because this value is created directly by and shared between users). We know that Facebook receives all the material benefits from our use. Most readers have probably already seen it calculated that with 850 million users and a speculative valuation of $100 billion, Facebook has netted $117.65 from each user. In this sense, we might say that the rate of exploitation is $117.65 per user for the eight years that Facebook has been in existence. However, without a concrete figure for the total value produced by each user, we are not really able to derive the real degree of exploitation. The best we can do is a sort of thought experiment: Would I pay $117.65 for what I have gotten out of Facebook in the past several years? If the answer is yes (personally speaking, I know I pay that much annually to host a website that I use far less than my profile), then we can loosely infer that the real degree of exploitation is less than 50%.
Why is important to know that the real degree of exploitation is less than 50%? Many critics of social media downplay the immaterial benefits of social media and argue that, because workers do not receive wages, they are experiencing “over-exploitation” (i.e., a condition where the real degree of exploitation approaches 100%). Our little thought experiment enables us to conclude that, while Facebook is exploitative (like all capitalist enterprise), it does not appear to be substantially more exploitative than conventional “brick and mortar” businesses. While all the alarm about hyper-capitalism and the precarious state of social media users is probably overstated, the fundamentally exploitative nature of Facebook’s business model gives users ample cause to be skeptical of the benevolent image of Facebook that founder and CEO Mark Zuckerberg painted in the IPO letter, saying “We don’t build services to make money; we make money to build better services.” Unfortunately for users, the fuzziness surrounding these economic relationships may make it easier than ever inducing this sort of “false consciousness.”
PJ Rey (@pjrey) Is co-founder and co-organizer for both the Cyborgology Blog and the Theorizing the Web conference. He is a PhD student in sociology at the University of Maryland. He is also the author of a related peer-reviewed article on the topic of “Alienation, Exploitation, and Social Media”, which is forthcoming in next edition of American Behavioral Scientist.
Pingback: Facebook, Labor, and the Possible Perils of Social Media « Organizations, Occupations and Work
Could we not also highlight however, that the immaterial aspects of facebook which confer value on it’s users are also aspects of the factory setting? In a factory setting workers also establish friendships and networks which are of value both to the organisation and to themselves and it is therefore sensible to consider the fact that the value being created by facebook users for themselves is separable from the surplus value being created for facebook’s owner. If we accept this view then Marx’s argument would continue to apply.
Sure, these form of value are seperable; in fact, the ability to simultaneously derive use-value and surplus-value is an important part of what defines the information economy. But the comparison between socialization on Facebook and in the factory is dubious. Sociality is necessary to the production of data in Facebook, while it is incidental and often discouraged in the factory. The old Fordist model, at least, would view this sort of socialization as time theft coming at the expense of productivity. So, rather that the production of sociality and surplus value being mutually reinforcing (as with Facebook), the two are in conflict in the factory.
I see the distinction that you’re drawing out, PJ. However, manufacturing is really a minority employer at this point (roughly 11% of private jobs in the U.S. last year). Do you see your analysis changing at all in post-Fordist world, where work is more flexible and more interactive in terms of relationships?
@Chris: Sure, the lines are fuzzier in a post-Fordist paradigm. The Italian autonomist lit regarding the “social factory” gets to the heart of this. But even there, the focus was on the production of “general intellect” and not on the individual data for marketing purposes. I think this is a relatively new phenomenon enabled by global networks and sophisticated databases. I’m not convinced it can be shoehorned in classic models. Marx was a good inductive theorist,talking about the factories that dominated his milieu; we should be equally willing to develop our own vocab to discuss new phenomena that confront us, I don’t think Marx “gets it wrong;” I just don’t he was trying to explains social media.
@PJ: I agree 100% about shoehorning. I’m interested to see where the discipline goes over the next few decades regarding the role of Marxist thought. As we move further and further away from the world Marx knew intimately, I think we’ll be forced more and more to, as you put it, developed our own vocab around these issues. Its an important theoretical project given the role that Marx as played in Sociology.
I also have another thought on your piece. You mentioned your willingness to pay ~$120 for access to Facebook over several years. My question is whether this really changes the reality of Facebook’s exploitation. Factory workers are paid wages, yet are still exploited. In this case you would be paying for the privilege to be exploited, assuming of course that what is happening on Facebook is akin to exploitation. This doesn’t sit right with me. Do you see where I’m coming from? This certainly moves us away from the shop floor, but I think we’re both in agreement that this is an important discussion to have – we just need new words for it. Even if this isn’t a classical example of Marxist exploitation, there still seems to be something there. A rose by another other name sort of thing.
As Facebook currently exists, exploitation is essential. Facebook is clearly deriving surplus value from the information commodities we are producing.
I think the situation would be somewhat different if we paid to use Facebook (and Facebook got out of the advertising business altogether). However, I think what makes you uncomfortable about just then imagining Facebook to be a conventional service provider (like say Verizon or Comcast) is that Facebook is fundamentally dependent on prosumption (i.e., not simple consumption). In this hypothetical scenario, we would not be paying to access content from 3rd party content producers (e.g., television studies); instead, we’d be paying to access our own content–paying to be exploited.
So, yes, I agree. The only reason I discussed the fact that many people would be willing to pay a significant sum to access Facebook, was to demonstrate that, even despite all the exploitation, users derive appreciable value from the site (therefore, it is not a case of “over-exploitation”). But, by no means does this refute fact that exploitation is built into the very fabric of Facebook.
>> Facebook is clearly deriving surplus value from the information commodities we are producing.
I’m not convinced by this. If one stops thinking in terms of cash and instead thinks in more general terms of value (as you do partially in your article) then at ~$120 for eight years of cultural, social, and symbolic capital aren’t we the one’s exploiting facebook?
I suppose the traditional Marxian response would be that Facebook doesn’t create value, only users create value. I agree that users derive a great deal of value from their collective activities on Facebook, but Facebook itself does not create that value. We should be careful not to fetishize Facebook. It is only a platform – only the means of production/consumption. Without the activities of it’s users, Facebook would have nothing to offer us. Thus, to say that users are exploiting Facebook is really to say that users are exploiting themselves, which is not exploitation at all.
Perhaps Facebook is even exploiting the rest of industry… When people use Facebook at work they’re typically already getting paid for what they should be doing. So Facebook not only gets people to work for them for free, it also has other companies pay people to work at Facebook.
Agreed! Excellent point!
Oops. That was me. Logged on a shared comp.